Creating
Mental Illness
by Allan V. Horwitz
University of Chicago Press, 2002.
Book Review by Lynn E. O'Connor, The Wright Institute, Berkeley,
California, USA.
Creating
Mental Illness, by sociologist, Allan V. Horwitz, is a fascinating
and scholarly critique of our classification of mental disorders.
Horwitz begins by stating boldly that many so-called mental disorders
according to our current symptom-based system of classification,
are not really mental disorders at all, but normal responses to
social stress, relationship problems, work or other problems in
living, or social deviance that may be in some cases, culturally
supported. He carefully defines "mental disorder" using
Wakefield's (1992; 1993) definition: "a mental disorder exists
when some internal psychological system is unable to function
as it is designed to function, and when this dysfunction is defined
as inappropriate in a particular social context". Prior to
the 1970s, psychiatry was heavily influenced by Freudian theory,
and mental disorders were seen as "non specific reflections
of unconscious mechanisms, not as discrete symptom-based diseases."
Psychopathology was vague and viewed as occurring on a continuum,
with the pathological merging into the normal. The early Diagnostic
and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (pre DSM-III) focused
on underlying conflicts and unconscious processes considered at
the time to be central to all people's mental problems. This Freudian
system allowed psychiatrists to spend less time treating the severe
mental disorders seen primarily in mental hospitals, and more
time treating the "neurosis" of normal people, which
were, according to dynamic psychiatry, not exactly normal. Horwitz
observes that it was the Freudians, through the pre DSM-III era,
who first pathologized the normal problems of living along with
personality and relationship problems in this vague continuous
classification, based on underlying unconscious mechanisms and
etiology. However, this system of classification, dynamic psychiatry,
wasn't amenable to research, it was unreliable -- one couldn't
assume that two different psychiatrists would diagnose the same
person similarly. Furthermore, in this system, symptoms were considered
unimportant in themselves, instead they too represented unconscious
processes. So this system of classification was problematic in
an increasingly science-based medicine.
Medicine was no longer accepting "case studies" as respectable
science, however they represented the only research that could
be done given the psychoanalytic framework. The premises of Freudian
theory could not meet the basic requirements of science -- they
included constructs and assumptions that could neither be falsified,
nor tested scientifically. For example, Horwitz notes "how
could anyone be shown NOT to have an oedipal complex when protestations
that one had no such desires were taken as evidence of resistance
to admitting its presence?
Freud, for example, interpreted
his patients' refusal to accept his interpretations of their symptoms
as confirmations of his theory of repression." Major concepts
in dynamic psychiatry, "especially the unconscious, were
inherently not subject to measurement and others, such as the
ego, id, and superego were too vague to be operationalized."
Therefore, the theory couldn't be tested by scientific method,
and was increasingly unacceptable to medicine in general. As the
result of this pressure on psychiatrists to get more scientific,
to keep up with the rest of medicine that was moving towards empirically
based and validated treatments, there was a rapid paradigm shift
in the field. It initially centered in a group of influential
and respected research psychiatrists at Washington University,
Saint Louis, and then extended broadly to the whole field as they
impacted the writing of the DSM-III.
The
Washington group wanted to classify mental disorders as categorical
rather than continuous and vague, such that they could be reliably
diagnosed and studied empirically, across samples and populations.
Returning to a Kraeplin-like, symptom based system of classification,
they developed 14 discrete disease entities, each with distinct
observable symptoms. Taking off from the work of the Washington
group and extending it to include a huge number of mental disorders
(well over 200) the DSM-III, appeared in 1980 and presented a
whole new system of classification, based on symptoms without
speculation about etiology and avoiding any particular theory
of psychopathology or psychotherapy. This new view of mental disorders
Horwitz called "diagnostic psychiatry." The new classification
system differed dramatically from the old. In dynamic psychiatry
mental illness was seen to occur on a continuum and were categorized
by vague and continuous unconscious mechanisms; in diagnostic
psychiatry mental illnesses were considered distinct categorical
entities with specific symptoms. From Horwitz's perspective, this
says this made sense for the psychotic disorders, for bipolar
disorder, for depression with psychotic features, but not for
the myriad of other problems for which people came to treatment.
Additionally,
in order to gain the support of the practicing clinicians as well
as those in research medicine/psychiatry, the authors of the DSM-III
went far beyond the 13 limited categories proposed by the Washington
group, and included all of the problems that clinicians were treating,
and that had initially been pathologized by the Freudians in the
earlier DSM. This included problems in living, responses to stresses,
problems in relationships, and the more pervasive personality
styles or the "personality disorders".
Horwitz
critiques both "dynamic psychiatry" (that is the diagnostic
schemas of theories of the Freudians) and "diagnostic psychiatry"
(that is the current field which supports a biological and symptom
based classification of mental illness). He suggests that many
problems that bring people to therapy are neither mental disorders
nor diseases, and neither system of classification allows for
this reality. Furthermore he says that outside of the psychotic
disorders, bipolar disorders and depression with psychotic features,
even those that are valid mental disorders, are not really discrete
categorical entities but are more realistically seen on a continuum.
For example he acknowledges that problems such as suicidal depression
in the absence of any external reason, crippling obsessions and
compulsions or phobias that prevent a person from living a reasonable
productive life, etc. are indeed mental disorders but he insists
that these are more accurately described as being continuous rather
than categorical.
Now
as a clinician I think about this distinction quite a bit. I am
rarely comfortable with the categorization of many of the personality
disorders, and I agree that personality problems are on a continuum.
However there are Axis I disorders (clinical syndromes) that I
believe fit the definition of mental disorder and are not so clearly
a matter of degree. For example depression (without psychotic
features), obsessive compulsive disorder, and panic disorder seem
quite discrete or categorical when they appear in the treatment
setting. However, I agree that personality disorders and the less
severe forms of anxiety and depression may be better described
as occurring on a continuum. I often say that in my work as a
practicing psychologist, initially I treat patients for mental
disorders (discrete, categorical clinical syndromes), then they
get better and I become an executive coach, or they only partly
get better and I try to help them with these less than discrete
personality problems.
Many
of the problems we treat, Horwitz defines as problems in living,
as non-pathological responses to life stresses such as divorce,
loss of job, illness in the family, aging parents, children with
difficulties in school etc. To classify these kinds of problems
as mental disorders is indeed turning the concept into one that
is basically a social construction, developed in response to political,
social, and economic pressure. Horwitz rather convincingly presents
evidence that some of the "new disorders" such as multiple
personality are in fact iatrogenic disorders, that is caused by
the therapists. He suggests that many of our more common disorders
in fashion today have also been caused by the culture of psychotherapy
so pervasive in our society. For example, he discusses how "social
phobia" has taken a naturally occurring temperament different,
namely shyness, and transformed it into a mental disorder that
is claimed to be common and pervasive, and treatable with SSRIs,
with a huge profit for the drug companies. Horwitz has a good
point.
After
taking us through the rapid transformation of our diagnostic system
of classification, the modern symptom-based DSM, Horwitz goes
on to describe the flaws in the epidemiological research by which
we have come to believe that disorders such as social phobia,
depression, or sexual dysfunction are far more common than in
fact they are. As he explains, when a clinician is making a diagnosis,
she asks the client a series of questions related to specific
symptoms, if they have ever been experienced and if so, how often,
for how long, and how severely, and in what context. For example,
the clinician may ask "have you ever felt depressed for more
than a two week period?", followed by a question about the
context, in order to discover if there was a precipitating factor
such as a divorce or a loss. I think we can all agree that for
a person to have experience a period of depression, more than
two weeks long, following a divorce or some other loss, is hardly
a mental disorder. So the clinician may make a diagnosis based
on symptoms, however context is the mediating factor. However,
as Horwitz describes it, in the epidemiological studies, people
are asked "have you ever felt depressed for more than a two
week period?" without obtaining the mediating situational
factors. Consequently, numerous people become a depression statistic,
when they were actually responding to a temporary situation such
as a recent loss. As a result, the frequencies of mental disorders
that these studies discover in the general population are highly
inflated.
The book also covers research on psychotherapy and drug treatment,
showing their strengths as well as their weaknesses. Horwitz isn't
exactly a social constructionist, he's not claiming that there
are no such things as mental disorders, or that mental illness
is a myth, or that mental illness is all a social construction.
But he makes a great case for questioning our diagnostic system
of classification and I came away from reading the book feeling
slightly humble. I found Horwitz's representation of biology and
the genetics of mental disorders to be more reductionistic than
is the actual state of biological psychiatry today----he seemed
more down on biological explanations than may be warranted and
from my perspective he makes too much of a distinction between
the biological and the social, as if they aren't entirely interdependent.
But Creating Mental Illness is a great read and I found it thought-provoking
and overall, I think the author has made an important observation
about weaknesses in our system of classification, and we would
be wise to reassess some of what we have accepted as gospel in
our field.